Affiliated with the University of Nicosia |
|||||
|
|||||
ETHNIC vs. CIVIC NATIONALISM IN BIETHNIC AND MULTIETHNIC STATES By Jerry Z. Muller
Professor of History, Catholic University of America
Keynote address at the annual dinner of the Cyprus Center for European and International Affairs, Nicosia, March 2009
|
|||||
The promise of social science is that it can provide useful guidance
based upon comparison. Social science attempts to derive valid
generalizations from a variety of cases, and based upon those
generalizations, to create classifications that are supposed to be
useful. Social science proceeds by trying to then fit particular cases
into some scheme of classification: classifications such as civic
nationalism versus ethnic nationalism, or “bi-ethnic states,” or
“multi-ethnic states.” If we say, for example, that Cyprus should be
classified as a bi-ethnic polity, we are implicitly promising that there
are other cases of bi-ethnic societies that are analogous, and by saying
that they are analogous, we are implicitly suggesting that there is
something significant to be learned from them. So too, when we use the
term “multi-ethnic states.”
But there is a problem with social scientific analogy —and that lies in
its relationship to empirical reality. It often seems that the less you
know about a particular case, the more it seems to resemble cases that
you do know. That is why
foreigners are so ready to dispense advice, and why they are so facile
in doing so.
But the more you know about a particular case, the more aware you are
that it is
not analogous to
other instances, instances that seem quite similar when seen from a
distance.
That is why you should beware of foreigners bearing advice.
So let me begin with some disappointing news: I will not present you
with a solution to “the Cyprus problem.” Rather, what I hope to be able
to provide are some broad historical perspectives and conceptual
distinctions that are relevant to thinking about the modern history of
Cyprus.
How we think about Cyprus (indeed how we think about almost
anything) depends on the historical framework into which we put it.
And that historical framework has changed with the end of the Cold War
and its aftermath.
In 1984, when Christopher Hitchens published his widely-read book,
Hostage to History: Cyprus from
the Ottomans to Kissinger, he treated the division of Cyprus and
ethnic separation that had occurred there as an exception. His book was
based on the implicit assumption that cooperation between ethnic groups
is the norm, and that one therefore needed an elaborate explanation of
why Greek and Turkish Cypriots were not living together in peace and
harmony. For Hitchens (as for other British leftists, such as Perry
Anderson), the explanation was ready at hand. The problem lay with
external powers, especially with the British, — who had split the Greek
and Turkish communities with a policy of divide and rule (as they had
supposedly done in India and Palestine as well) — and the Americans,
above all Henry Kissinger, who had subordinated the needs of Cypriots to
those of America’s Cold War allies, especially Turkey. There are many
variations of this theme: what they have in common is the tacit
assumption that ethnic cooperation should be regarded as the norm, and
that ethnic conflict is thus in need of special explanation. I’ve chosen
Hitchens’ book because his broad perspective seems to be widely shared
in the Republic of Cyprus.
But this view was grounded in a perspective that was foreshortened, both
geographically and chronologically. Hitchens writes, for example, that
“Cyprus was the only part of Europe to be part of a modern European
empire.” But that is quite wrong. Much of central and Eastern Europe in
the twentieth century was part either of the Habsburg empire, or the
Romanov empire, or — at the time Hitchens was writing — of the Soviet
empire.
How did Hitchens and those like him account for inter-ethnic conflict in
Cyprus: for the intercommunal violence of 1958, 1963, of 1974, and the
large scale ethnic transfers, above all the expulsions of Greek Cypriots
from the northern zone, but also of course the movement of Turkish
Cypriots from the south to the northern zone? All of this was seen as
anomalous, unexpected, exceptional, judged against the experience of
Europe since 1948 or so, which was seen as the relevant time frame, Here
Hitchens was in many ways echoing common wisdom in Western Europe and
the United States. The reigning assumption was that ethnic nationalism
was a detour from the main road of modernity, which led, inevitably and
desirably, to civic nationalism. By civic nationalism we mean a form of
belonging which includes everyone within the borders of the state,
regardless of their origin. Civic nationalism was defined by adherence
to a shared set of laws or ideals, however minimally defined. It was
said to be oriented to the future, not to the past. Ethnic nationalism,
by contrast, was based upon shared origins: of blood, religion, or
language. Civic nationalism was seen as characteristic of the United
States, Britain, France, and increasingly of the rest of Europe —and in
the future, of the rest of the world as well.
Today our perspective has changed. After the collapse of the Soviet
Empire, the events that followed in the former Soviet empire, and the
new attention of historians to other elements of twentieth century
history, we are more likely to see what occurred in Cyprus as a rather
typical example of
post-imperial ethnonational disaggregation, stretching from the era
before WWI through the end of the century. As Niall Ferguson pointed out
in his history of the twentieth century,
The War of the World,
(2006), the twentieth century was the bloodiest in modern
history. Among the reasons for this was the decline of empires, and the
ethnic conflict that often followed in its wake.
Why was ethnic conflict so frequent?
Much of it has to do with a change of collective expectations. In
empires, there is no expectation of the likeness of ruler and ruled. In
empires, such as the Ottoman empire, or the Romanov empire, there is no
assumption that those who rule will be fundamentally similar to those
who are ruled. As Elie Kedourie pointed out, these earlier political
understandings were upset by the doctrine of collective self-rule, or
self-determination, that is, by the doctrine of democracy. But the
doctrine of democracy cannot answer a fundamental question, namely “Who
is the demos?” That is, what group is to be included in the polity and
what group isn’t? Or to put it another way, who is the “self” in
“self-government”?
The most frequent answer to this question was that self-rule was the
rule of a particular ethnos. Hence the primacy in modern history of
ethnic nationalism, defined in a variety of ways, some more liberal and
inclusive, others more exclusive and intolerant. In areas of mixed
ethnicity, the spread of the doctrine of collective self-determination
frequently led to conflict over which group would dominate.
In recent years we have seen the decline of the assumption that the end
of empires meant triumph of civic nationalism. Indeed, historians have
increasingly called the very dichotomy between civic and ethnic
nationalism into question. It has been pointed out that civic
nationalism was most dominant in areas of Europe that already had a high
degree of cultural homogeneity, such as England, Sweden, France:
countries that had long been under a single ruler and had gone through
processes of cultural homogenization. Sometimes their relative
homogeneity was grounded in the fact that large minorities had been
expelled; think of the French expulsion of the Huguenots in 1685.
To some degree, ethnic and cultural homogeneity seemed to be a
prerequisite for liberal
democracy. That, at least, that was the opinion of many liberal thinkers
before the twentieth century. Take this example:
“Providence has been pleased to give this one connected country to one
united people – a people descended from the same ancestors, speaking the
same language, professing the same religion, attached to the same
principles of government, very similar in their manners and
customs…who…have nobly established their general liberty and
independence.”
Now this may read like a classic enunciation of ethnic nationalist
doctrine. In fact, it stems from John Jay, an American, and one of the
authors of
The Federalist Papers
writing in 1788.
Or consider this view and its author:
“Free institutions are next to impossible in a country made up of
different nationalities. Among a people without fellow-feelings,
especially if they read and speak different languages, the united public
opinion necessary to the working of representative institutions cannot
exist…”
This comes from John Stuart Mill, perhaps the greatest British liberal
thinker of the nineteenth century, writing in 1861.
A comparative perspective shows that beyond western Europe, civic
nationalism was most prominent as an ideal in what are sometimes called
settler states, where the indigenous population had been wiped out or
marginalized, in countries such as the United Sates, Australia, and
Canada. And when thinking about historical comparisons, it remains
essential to keep in mind that the United States and Australia, while
made up of people of multiple ethnic origins, are
not multi-ethnic in the way
that India, or Nigeria are; nor bi-ethnic in the way that Cyprus is. For
a key factor in the United States and Australia is their mono-linguality,
that is, the fact that there is one dominant language, which everyone
either speaks or aspires to have their children speak. That creates a
basis for common understandings and for ease of communication that one
does not find in bi-ethnic societies, and certainly not in multi-ethnic
states that are also multi-lingual, such as India or Nigeria or
Pakistan.
When we look at the history of Europe and of the post-colonial societies
beyond it during the twentieth century, what we find is a history of
ethnic disaggregation, often violent, stretching from milder forms of
coercion through forced expulsion and ethnic cleansing and, at the
extreme, genocide.
Massive ethnic disaggregation began on the frontiers of Europe on the
eve of the First World War. In the Balkans, wars to expand the nation
states of Bulgaria, Greece, and Serbia at the expense of the ailing
Ottoman empire were accompanied by ferocious inter-ethnic violence.
During the Balkan Wars of 1912-1913, almost half a million people left
their existing homelands, either voluntarily or by force. Muslims left
regions under the control of Greeks, Bulgarians, and Serbs; Bulgarians
abandoned Greek-controlled areas of Macedonia; and Greeks fled from
regions of Macedonia ceded to Bulgaria and Serbia.
Under the impact of World War I, the three great turn-of-the-century
empires all broke up, unleashing an explosion of ethnonationalism. In
Turkey, mass deportations and murder took the lives of a million members
of the suspect Armenian minority, in an early attempt at ethnic
cleansing, if not genocide. Shortly after the war came the massive
exchange of ethnic populations between Greece and Turkey, formalized in
the Treaty of Lausanne of 1923. In the process, the Turks expelled
almost 1.5 million ethnic Greeks from Turkey into Greece; the Greeks, in
turn, expelled almost 400,000 Muslims from Greece into Turkey.
Out of the breakup of the Romanov and Habsburg empires there emerged a
multitude of new nation states. Many conceived of themselves as
ethno-national states (though they were actually multi-ethnic), in which
the state existed to protect and promote the dominant ethnic group.
Generally, nationalist governments openly discriminated in favor of the
dominant nationality, and against minority groups. Thus, inter-war
eastern Europe became a cauldron of ethnic tensions.
The politics of ethnonationalism took a yet more deadly turn during the
Second World War. The National Socialist regime tried to reorder the
ethnic map of Europe using means more violent than had ever been
contemplated. The most well known act of the regime was its most
radical: the attempt to eliminate the Jews of Europe by murdering them
all — a policy in which the regime largely succeeded. Beyond this, the
regime made use of the ethnic German minorities in Czechoslovakia,
Poland, and elsewhere to enforce Nazi domination. All of this would have
tremendous repercussions when the war ended.
The defeat of the Axis powers set the stage for another massive round of
ethnonational transformation. The wave of ethnic expulsions in the
second half of the 1940s was larger than any other before or since. The
political settlement in central Europe that followed the First World War
had been achieved primarily by moving borders over populations to bring
about national homogeneity.
At the
end of World War II, this attempt to move borders around people was
judged a failure. Instead there was massive movement of people across
borders to realize the same goal. From the autumn of 1944 to mid-1945,
five million Germans fled westward from the eastern parts of the German
Reich in the face of the conquering Red Army, From 1945 to 1947, the
new, post-liberation regimes in Czechoslovakia, Poland, Yugoslavia and
Hungary expelled another seven million ethnic Germans. The collaboration
of the German diasporic minorities in eastern Europe with the Third
Reich made them the objects of hatred. In total, over twelve million
Germans were expelled westward, the largest such population movement in
European history. The few surviving Jews who returned to post-war Poland
were met by a wave of anti-semitic murder, and most made their way to
the new Jewish home in Israel. In addition to the ethnic Germans and
surviving Jews, another seven million refugees from other ethnic groups
were evicted from their homes and resettled after the war. In order to
make the ethnic population correspond to the new borders, 1,500,000
Poles living in areas that now became part of the USSR were deported to
Poland. 500,000 ethnic Ukrainians living in Poland were sent to the
Ukrainian Soviet Republic.
Yet another exchange of populations took place between Hungary and
Czechoslovakia, as Slovaks were transferred out of Hungary to
Czechoslovakia, while Magyars were sent from Slovakia to Hungary. A
smaller exchange took place between Hungary and Yugoslavia: Magyars went
from Yugoslavia to Hungary, Serbs and Croats moved in the opposite
direction. Thus, a few years
after the end of the Second World War, the ethnonational ideal had
largely been realized in most of Europe, as each state was comprised of
a single ethnic group.
From 1945 through 1989, the few exceptions to this rule included
Czechoslovakia, Yugoslavia, and of course the Soviet Union. Their
subsequent fate demonstrated the ongoing vitality of ethnonationalism.
After the fall of communism, East and West Germany were unified with
remarkable rapidity. Czechoslovakia — the model bi-ethnic state—split
peacefully into Czech and Slovak republics. The Soviet Union was
disaggregated into a series of nation states. Another multi-ethnic
state, Yugoslavia, saw the secession of Croatia and Slovenia, and then
descended into ethnonational wars over Bosnia and Kosovo.
Much of the history of the post-colonial world is one of ethnonational
struggle in the wake of the colonial empires. There were frequent bouts
of inter-ethnic violence, often followed by partition, and by forced
expulsion and “voluntary” migration, that was often a response to
perceived threats brought on by actual violence. The end of the British
Raj in 1947 brought about the partition of the colony into India and
Pakistan, and an orgy of violence between Hindus, Muslims, and Sikhs,
that took hundreds of thousands of lives. Fifteen million people became
refugees:
Muslims who found
homes in Pakistan, and Hindus who migrated from Pakistan to India. The
post-colonial multi-ethnic entity of Pakistan subsequently dissolved in
1971 into Pakistan and Bangladesh.
In the former British mandate of Palestine, a Jewish state was
established in 1948, with plans for an Arab state as well. Jewish
sovereignty was opposed by the Arab world, and was greeted first by
revolts by the indigenous Arabs and then by invasion from the
surrounding Arab states. In the war that resulted, regions that fell
under Arab control were cleansed of their Jewish population. Arabs fled
or were coerced from many of the areas that came under Jewish control,
Some 750,000 Arabs departed, primarily into the surrounding Arab
countries, while the remaining 150,000 became a minority in the new
Jewish state (comprising more than a sixth of its population). In the
several years that followed, nationalist-inspired violence against Jews
in Arab countries led to the end of this second locus of Jewish diaspora
life, and over 700,000 Jews left their lands of origin in the Arab world
and emigrated to Israel.
When we look at modern history through these lenses, what happened in
Cyprus during the period of British colonial control and after seems
typical, namely the redefinition of group identities along
ethno-national lines. That is not because ethno-nationalism was a
backward ideology foisted upon Greek and Turkish Cypriots by the wily
British. It was because ethnonationalist ideology was deeply intertwined
with becoming modern. For modern ideologies are grounded upon the idea
of self-determination. And the spread of the idea of self-determination
necessarily raised the issue of who was included in the group that was
to do the determining, and that was defined, as so frequently was the
case elsewhere, in terms of ethnic identity. What happened after the end
of British rule in Cyprus does not seem anomalous; sadly, it was all too
typical.
The comity and peace of contemporary Europe, seen through these lenses,
was due not so much to the triumph of the ideals of civic nationalism as
the realization of the ethnonationalist ideal in so much of Europe. That
seems to have led to a waning of ethnic nationalism (though by no means
its disappearance), which may have been a prerequisite for the
development of the European Union.
Ethnonational and civic national states each have their own advantages
and disadvantages. The advantages of ethnonational states often include
a greater sense of solidarity, of common fate. That, in turn, is often
linked to increased trust, which diminishes transaction costs, such as
extensive (and expensive) legal guarantees that are required when trust
is missing. The advantages of civic national states include the
potential for greater mutual fructification of ways of life, a greater
ease of borrowing from one group to another that may be culturally
creative. Civic nationalism also has the ability to link a wider range
of people. But civic nationalism can’t just be created
ex nihilo – must have a basis
in historical experience. And this brings us back to the issue of
bi-ethnic and multi-ethnic states, states usually constituted by one or
another form of federalism.
There is by now a huge literature on federalist constitution-making. But
as the wisest analysts of federalism have noted, constitutions are
rarely the source of political success or political failure. For
constitutions reflect political will at a particular point in time.
Political will, like political identity, is of course dynamic. The
desire to live in one polity rather than another is often influenced by
economic and political factors. This may change, not through a single
act of constitution-making, but by the build-up of trust over time, as
each side comes to see the advantage of co-operation with the other.
Citizens within a democratic federation may in theory have dual but
complimentary political identities, for example, as Cypriots and as
Greeks, as Cypriots and as Turks. But that is in theory, and the reality
may be quite different.
The British political theorist, David Miller, has distinguished three
models of multi-ethnic state arrangements. There are states that involve
ethnic cleavages within a single polity (as in Switzerland), There are
states composed of rival nationalities, each of which are inward-looking
and exclusive (as in Czechoslovakia, or Israel.) And then there are
federal systems based on nested identities: of multiple
territorially-based political communities, which are themselves part of
a larger nation-state (as is the case of Catalonia in Spain, Scotland in
the United Kingdom, or Quebec in Canada.) Which of these models applies
— single state with ethnic cleavages, rival nationalities, or nested
identities —depends in part on the degree of cultural overlap, mutual
economic advantage, and interwoven positive history between the groups
in question. It seems to me that Greek Cypriots would like to think that
the model of nested identities applies to Cyprus. But it may well be a
case of rival nationalities – more like Czechs and Slovaks, or more
probably like Israelis and Palestinians, than like Scots and Great
Britain or Catalonia and Spain.
When looking at multi-ethnic states, and especially at bi-ethnic states,
I think that what is striking is the ongoing uncertainty and constant
renegotiation built into such structures. In the case of Czechoslovakia,
a bi-ethnic state ended through a peaceable break-up. In the case of
Belgium, tensions between the two main ethnic groups recently led to a
year-long stalemate in forming a government. Take the most favorable
case, of Canada, where there are 7 million Quebecois (83% of whom are
French speaking) versus 24 million Anglophone Canadians. The meaning of
federalism, there as elsewhere, is itself a matter of ongoing debate and
ambiguity, perhaps a strategic ambiguity, in which each side is more
content because the other sides differing understanding of the situation
is not made fully explicit.
And so, as promised, I have no solution to “the Cyprus question.” But
perhaps these historical and comparative reflections will help you to
see it in a slightly different light. |
|||||
|
|||||
Cyprus Center for European and
International Affairs Copyright © 2009. All rights reserved |
|
||||
Makedonitissis 46, 2417 Egkomi CYPRUS | P.O.Box 24005, 1700 CYPRUS t: +35722841600 | f: +35722357964 | cceia@unic.ac.cy | www.cceia.unic.ac.cy |